Crito

by

Plato

Teachers and parents! Our Teacher Edition on Crito makes teaching easy.

Crito Summary & Analysis

Summary
Analysis
It is 399 BC in Athens, and Socrates sits condemned in prison, awaiting his execution. No one knows exactly when it will come, as a religious festival is taking place on the nearby island of Delos, and Athens has sent a delegation; no executions may take place before it returns. In the meantime, Socrates sits, sleeps, and waits.
Crito opens with Socrates in solemn contemplation before his death. The setting is not without pathos; isolated from his city and community, Socrates is left alone with his own mind.
Themes
Dying Well Theme Icon
At early dawn, Socrates wakes up to find his friend and student, Crito, in his cell. Socrates is surprised that the guards let him in, but Crito explains that he bribed them. Socrates also wonders why Crito didn’t wake him when he entered. Crito explains that he let Socrates sleep as a kindness; if he himself were about to be executed, Crito says, he wouldn’t want to lie awake waiting for death a moment longer than he had to.
An old friend interrupts Socrates’ isolation––a necessary premise for a dialogue, the standard literary vehicle of Platonic philosophy, to begin. Crito tries to empathize with Socrates’ situation by letting him sleep, assuming that Socrates must be as scared as he himself would be, In other words, Crito assumes that they share a basic attitude towards death.
Themes
Dying Well Theme Icon
Crito sees, however, that Socrates appears completely untroubled by his impending death. He mentions this to Socrates, who merely counters that someone as old as he is shouldn’t “resent” death. Crito notes that most people his age “resent” it all the same. Socrates admits this, but changes the subject, asking Crito why he’s come so early.
Socrates shows Crito that his attempt at empathizing has failed. Apparently, Socrates’ concept of death is not only completely at odds with Crito’s, but also with that of the average view of someone his age. Socrates’ conclusions issue a challenge both to public opinion and to what someone like Crito might consider common sense.
Themes
Truth and Public Opinion Theme Icon
Dying Well Theme Icon
Quotes
Crito explains that he comes as the bearer of bad news: the ship that carried the Athenian delegation to Delos is expected to return today, allowing executions to resume the next day. If true, this means Socrates will die tomorrow.
Crito tries to impress Socrates with the urgency of his situation, hoping to inspire him to take some sort of action to save himself. Through Crito’s words and actions, it’s clear that he’s fearful of death and believes that Socrates must do something to avoid such a supremely awful fate. In other words, Crito seems to think that there’s no such thing as a good time or a good way to die—a mindset Socrates will soon challenge.
Themes
Dying Well Theme Icon
Get the entire Crito LitChart as a printable PDF.
Crito PDF
Socrates is of a different opinion. He describes a dream he had the previous night in which he was visited by a beautiful woman in white who delivered a divinely inspired message: “Socrates, may you arrive at fertile Phthia on the third day.” Assuming that this dream implies that he will die in three days, he deduces that the ship won’t return for two.
Again, Socrates shows himself to be operating under a completely different set of assumptions than Crito. Socrates’ dream hints that he somehow has access to a degree of divine wisdom, which seems to allow him to know things Crito doesn’t.
Themes
Truth and Public Opinion Theme Icon
Quotes
Crito has no interest in talking about dreams. He believes that Socrates must escape from the prison immediately, and he has come to offer his help in doing so. He frames this escape as imperative not just for Socrates, but for Crito himself: he wishes neither to lose Socrates, nor for the people of Athens to believe he was unwilling to pay the money to save Socrates’ life.
Recognizing that Socrates is thinking along very different lines, Crito attempts to convince Socrates to escape prison through a short, emotional argument which relies on the bonds of love and care between Socrates, his friends, and his family.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Quotes
Socrates criticizes Crito for being overly concerned with what other people think. The common people of Athens, he says, can believe what they will. Ultimately, their opinion has nothing to do with what’s right and wrong. Crito disagrees. Socrates’ own case, he says, proves that popular opinion can mean the difference between life and death. Socrates is unfazed. The people can put someone to death, but both “the greatest evils” and “the greatest good” lie beyond their reach.
Once again, Socrates hints somewhat cryptically at his access to a deeper kind of knowledge, this time concerning the nature of good and evil. Crito considers death one of the worst things that can befall a person, but Socrates disagrees. Because of this disagreement, Crito is much more afraid of the punishments the public can inflict than Socrates is. This disagreement uncovers the first argumentative distinction between the two characters’ worldviews.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Truth and Public Opinion Theme Icon
Quotes
Crito tries again. He wonders if Socrates is hesitant to escape because he’s worried that his friends would get in trouble with the authorities if they broke him out of prison. He attempts to reassure him, promising that Socrates’ life is worth the risk. But Socrates doesn’t engage with this line of argument at all, except to affirm that “I do have these things in mind, Crito, and also many others.”
Crito neglects to pursue his analytical disagreements with Socrates, preferring to keep the problem in personal terms. Unable to understand Socrates’ objections to escaping, he tries anticipating them on his own by assuring him that he and others are willing to sacrifice for his well-being.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Political Obligation Theme Icon
Crito keeps at it, listing all the people and foreign governments that would be willing to help Socrates. This time, though, he expands his argument, adding that he considers it unjust for Socrates to die when given the opportunity to live, as he would be abandoning his sons and his loved ones. Crito begs Socrates once again to think of how his death would reflect on his friends who had the ability to save him, lest they be accused of “cowardice and unmanliness.”
As Crito’s pleas become increasingly emotional, they begin to sound like accusations. He reproaches Socrates for neglecting an assumed moral obligation to his kin. For Crito, virtue hinges on supporting one’s friends and family above all, even if that means rejecting the law in the process. In addition, this switch in registers indicates that Crito is willing to adjust his arguments in order to convince Socrates to do what he wants.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Political Obligation Theme Icon
Dying Well Theme Icon
Quotes
Socrates insists that the matter must be decided through argument and reflection. He tells Crito to remember how he has always approached such questions in the past, and asks him whether the fact of his impending execution should be enough to undo all the beliefs and principles by which he lives.
Socrates senses the sincerity of Crito’s argument, along with its rather jagged logical progression. He challenges him to think not just of the emotionally charged personal issues at stake, but to argue consistently based on the general principles that guide his life. With this, Socrates begins to flesh out the idea of consistently living in accordance with one’s values as a means to a virtuous life.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Dying Well Theme Icon
Quotes
From here, Socrates begins the dialogue in earnest. He asks Crito if one should only care for the opinions of the wise rather than the foolish. After Crito agrees, Socrates expands on this thought, comparing the opinions of fools about justice to the opinions of laymen about medicine. Taking advice on medicine from someone who isn’t a doctor could harm the body; likewise, taking advice on justice from someone who is not wise harms “that part of ourselves that is improved by just actions and destroyed by unjust actions.” At Socrates’ prompting, Crito affirms every step of this argument.
Socrates insists on beginning the dialogue by finding a basic principle which both he and Crito share: that one should only care what wise people think. After establishing this common ground, he then makes a large jump from this principle by asserting that wisdom concerning moral questions is analogous to the specialized expertise of a doctor. The logic of this leap is not obvious, but Crito is a rather passive dialogue partner, so for now he merely assents.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Truth and Public Opinion Theme Icon
Socrates asks Crito whether the part of the self “destroyed by unjust actions” is more or less valuable than the health of the body. Crito replies that it is more valuable. Socrates replies that this shows that one should not care for the opinion of the majority, but for that of those who understand justice.
Here, Socrates develops his argument on wisdom by adding that one’s moral “health” is more important than one’s physical health. Once again, this addition is not analytically justified, but Crito agrees all the same. In elevating moral health above physical health, Socrates gestures to the idea that in order to live a truly virtuous life, one must consistently stick to their principles.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Truth and Public Opinion Theme Icon
Carrying the argument forward, Socrates asks why it matters so much that the majority is able to put him to death. He and Crito agree that “the good life, the beautiful life, and the just life” are one and the same. Accordingly, the ability to live a good life becomes contingent on acting justly. If continuing to live would mean living unjustly, then, Socrates concludes, he must die.
Socrates articulates a major tenet of Platonic philosophy: that goodness, beauty, and justice––at least to the extent that a human life can model them––are the same thing. In combination with the previous step, this argument leads him and Crito to agree that dying justly is better than living unjustly.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Political Obligation Theme Icon
Dying Well Theme Icon
Quotes
Having reached agreement on this point, Socrates starts another discussion, adding that he considers it “important” to persuade Crito of the reasoning behind his choices. He recalls that they have always agreed that one must always attempt to avoid doing wrong, and asks if public opinion has suddenly acquired any relevance to that question. Crito admits that it hasn’t, affirming their shared conviction that one must never do wrong.
Up to this point, the dialogue has mostly consisted of Socrates repeating basic elements of his belief system and eliciting Crito’s agreement. He now announces his intention to apply these first principles to develop an argument specific enough to dictate the proper course of action in his own case.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Truth and Public Opinion Theme Icon
Dying Well Theme Icon
Quotes
Socrates explores the implications of this belief, asking Crito whether it is acceptable to, for example, act wrongly as revenge for a wrong committed against oneself. Following from their previously stated convictions, Crito asserts that this would not be acceptable, and agrees with Socrates that a person must never act wrongly, regardless of the wrongs inflicted against them.
Having agreed that one should always try to avoid doing evil, Socrates crafts a more specific argument against the morality of revenge. He and Crito never directly articulate what counts as committing a wrong, apparently taking a shared definition for granted, despite this definition’s central importance to the argument.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Socrates seizes on this moment, claiming that Crito does not really share this belief as he claims to. He promises to show him how. Socrates then provides an example, asking whether it is just to break an agreement one has reached with someone. When Crito agrees that this would be unjust, Socrates returns to the matter at hand, asking Crito if his escape would not be “harming people whom we should least do harm to.” Crito is baffled by the way the argument has progressed and feels unable to answer the question.
In this passage, Socrates highlights the importance of living consistently in accordance with one’s personal values. By promising to show Crito that he does not truly hold the beliefs he professes, Socrates shows once again that he thinks more deeply than Crito: he can apparently anticipate the course of the discussion to come before it’s even begun. This promise provides the chance to turn the discussion from abstract morality to concrete matters of law and government.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Political Obligation Theme Icon
Socrates proceeds by speaking rhetorically as the “laws and the state,” or the nomoi, asking if it’s possible to ignore the verdicts of a court without implying that the courts have no validity. That would mean nothing less than attempting to destroy the city by undermining its laws.
The “laws” which Socrates personifies here are more than just the written statutes of Athens; the Greek word used here (nomoi) also refers to the customs and institutions of the polity. By pretending to personify the laws, Socrates implies that these institutions are sufficiently unified and consistent to speak with a single voice.
Themes
Political Obligation Theme Icon
Crito counters, at Socrates’ suggestion, by asserting that the law acted wrongly towards Socrates by condemning him; for that reason, one can disobey it. Still speaking as the laws, Socrates does not contradict that a wrong was committed, but argues that he is nevertheless bound to obey the state.
Socrates distinguishes between wrongs committed through the “laws” and wrongs committed by the laws themselves. He puts his own guilty verdict in the former category.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Political Obligation Theme Icon
Before allowing Crito to break in, Socrates insists on explaining where this obligation comes from. He lists the goods he received from the state, arguing that there are so many of these goods that any citizen must accord the state a position of honor even greater than that of their parents. If it is impious to disrespect one’s mother or father, it is even worse to disrespect the state, even if it “leads you to war to be wounded or killed.” A just citizen can only obey the state or convince it to act differently. Crito agrees.
Socrates outlines the first two parts of his three-step argument for total loyalty to the state: that a person owes the state for what they receive from it, and that the state always provides the opportunity to convince it to change its intended course of action. Both of these arguments apply specifically to Athens, a state rich enough to provide many benefits and mostly governed by democratic institutions; it is unclear how they might apply to other states where this is not the case.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Political Obligation Theme Icon
Though he has already elicited Crito’s agreement, Socrates keeps pushing. He observes that any Athenian of age has the right to leave the city and go somewhere else if he dislikes the law. Escaping prison would therefore be wrong for three reasons: first, it would be equivalent to disobeying his “parents”; second, because he had already been given the opportunity to convince the state to act differently in court, and therefore had already had a fair shot at disputing its intended course of action; and third, because he had spent his whole life in the city, and thereby consented to obey its laws.
Freedom of movement becomes the third leg of Socrates’ argument, despite the fact that economic and political conditions often made “going elsewhere” more difficult than Socrates’ words would indicate. Most significantly, the argument also makes no effort to account for the enormous segments of the population which were not considered citizens, including women and slaves. This failure significantly limits the general applicability of Socrates’ argument.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Political Obligation Theme Icon
Socrates now applies these arguments to his own case. He justifies this by repeating that he has stayed in the city his whole life and taken advantage of the goods it offered, and even had children there. This, he argues, means that he was “satisfied” with the law and the state of Athens. Furthermore, at his trial, he stated that he preferred death to exile. Contradicting that belief, together with his agreement to follow Athens’ laws, would make him like “the meanest type of slave.” He asks Crito if he agrees. He does.
Continuing the dialogue’s trend, Socrates only addresses specifics after establishing the general principles which will dictate his engagement with them. He stresses the importance of absolute logical consistency, comparing inconsistency to slavery as a wretched and shameful condition. These statements elicit Crito’s immediate agreement.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Political Obligation Theme Icon
Here, Socrates takes a moment to return to Crito’s earlier argument that dying would mean abandoning his friends and children. He points out that those same friends would stand in danger of retribution if he escaped successfully.
Socrates reveals that his decision includes some consideration for his loved ones after all. It remains unclear how this point fits into the arguments about citizenship he made above, or whether he adds it merely for the sake of refuting Crito as thoroughly as possible.
Themes
Dying Well Theme Icon
Addressing another one of Crito’s points, Socrates imagines what his life would be like in a new city. If he went to a well-governed city, he says, the people would look on him with justified suspicion as one who had already showed his contempt for the law. On the other hand, if he went to Crito’s friends in Thessaly, he would be forced to live a hard life amid political instability and chaos, making it difficult to give his children a good life. If he dies, however, he can count on his friends to take care of his family.
Socrates’ arguments become even more practical, showing his sensitivity to the contemporary political situation in Greece. He also hints further towards an unelaborated philosophy of kinship, indicating that he recognizes obligations to his family and expects loyalty from his friends (both institutions being at least partially determined by the Athenian “laws”).
Themes
Political Obligation Theme Icon
Dying Well Theme Icon
Quotes
Socrates, still pretending to speak as the law of Athens, concludes his argument by considering his own fate after death. If Socrates dies willingly, the laws declare that he can count on the “rulers” of the underworld to defend him, since he has been wronged “not by us, the laws, but by men.” If he flees, on the other hand, he will live a wretched life among the living and can expect that things will be no less wretched after death.
Socrates returns to divine matters, vaguely indicating his belief in some sort of important moral judgment after death. It remains unclear how this belief influences his views on the nature of good and evil, if at all; the dialogue’s mentions of divine things serve only to demonstrate Socrates’ connection to immortal truths that Crito does not understand.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Political Obligation Theme Icon
Dying Well Theme Icon
Quotes
Socrates turns to his old friend and addresses him directly. He tells Crito that he hears the words of the “laws” around him, like the music of the flutes of the Corybants, and the “echo of these words […] makes it impossible for [him] to hear anything else.” He invites Crito to continue to object if he thinks he can still make a case for his proposal; for his own part, however, he declares the argument closed.
Socrates’ words sound increasingly mystical as he reports an experience of divine inspiration, balancing out the prophetic dream he mentioned at the dialogue’s beginning. This mysticism adds an extra degree of mystery and allure to his character.
Themes
The Virtuous Life Theme Icon
Political Obligation Theme Icon
Dying Well Theme Icon
Quotes
Crito concedes, resigned and defeated: “I have nothing to say, Socrates.” Socrates accepts this concession, bidding Crito to make his peace with things: “let it be then, Crito, and let us act in this way, since this is the way the god is leading us.”
Crito refuses to admit that he has been proven wrong, but gives up all the same. The dialogue concludes with his somber goodbye to his old friend, further impressing the reader with the setting’s intense emotional charge. Socrates’ parting words suggest that living by consistent and well-reasoned principles liberates him from the fear and concern that Crito is clearly still riddled with. In other words, the good philosopher has no reason to fear death.
Themes
Dying Well Theme Icon