Talking to Strangers

Talking to Strangers

by

Malcolm Gladwell

Teachers and parents! Our Teacher Edition on Talking to Strangers makes teaching easy.

Talking to Strangers: Chapter 2 Summary & Analysis

Summary
Analysis
1. On August 28, 1938, Neville Chamberlain, the British prime minister, met with his advisor to discuss the crisis of Adolf Hitler’s threat to invade the Sudetenland, a German-speaking area of Czechoslovakia, which likely would lead to a world war.  Complicating matters was the fact that in the late 1930s, Hitler’s intentions—and Hitler himself—remained largely unknown to most of the world’s leaders. Furthermore, hardly any world leaders had been able to meet the man in person.
Despite very publicly transforming Germany into a one-party dictatorship since his election as chancellor in 1933, Hitler’s secrecy makes him a stranger to other world leaders like Chamberlain. Here, Gladwell introduces another example in which failing to make sense of a stranger has dire, far-reaching consequences.  
Themes
Default to Truth Theme Icon
Chamberlain was determined to learn more about the elusive Hitler and determine if he could be trusted or reasoned with. On September 14, Chamberlain sent a letter to Hitler’s foreign minister, Joachim von Ribbentrop, to request a meeting with Hitler. Hitler agreed to meet, and polls across Great Britain showed that 70 percent of the country believed the meeting would help avoid a war. 
Like the CIA, Montezuma II, and Officer Encinia, Chamberlain believed he could rely on a combination of intuition and logic to determine whether he could trust a stranger.
Themes
Default to Truth Theme Icon
Self vs. Stranger  Theme Icon
Chamberlain arrived in Munich on September 15 and met Hitler at his retreat outside Berchtesgaden. Hitler voiced his enthusiasm to seize the Sudetenland but made it clear that this was all he wanted. Chamberlain returned to England, satisfied with the meeting and confident that he could trust the man’s word. He would return to Germany to negotiate with Hitler two more times. 
Something about Hitler’s demeanor convinced Chamberlain that he could trust Hitler’s word. Chamberlain seems to believe that a link exists between a person’s external behavior and their internal motivations. As history will reveal, Chamberlain was woefully misguided in trusting Hitler. 
Themes
Default to Truth Theme Icon
Limitations of Transparency  Theme Icon
Quotes
2. History sees Chamberlain’s negotiations with Hitler as having been completely botched by Chamberlain’s misreading of him. How such a misreading could happen is a mystery, since Chamberlain insists that he kept meticulous track of Hitler’s mannerisms and found him to be “rational, determined,” and trustworthy. Gladwell argues that in believing he could trust Hitler, Chamberlain fell victim to the common misunderstanding that we can trust the information we glean from personal interactions with strangers.
History blames Chamberlain for failing to detect deceit in Hitler. Gladwell is sympathetic toward Chamberlain, however, suggesting that his misreading of Hitler as a “rational, determined” person is less a consequence of Chamberlain’s gullibility than it is a natural human instinct to trust that people are being truthful. Essentially, nobody wants to believe everyone is lying to them.
Themes
Default to Truth Theme Icon
Self vs. Stranger  Theme Icon
Get the entire Talking to Strangers LitChart as a printable PDF.
Talking to Strangers PDF
While one might blame Chamberlain’s misreading of Hitler on his naivete and inexperience in foreign affairs, Gladwell counters this with the argument that Hitler deceived many other foreign officials as well. Lord Halifax, an aristocrat who would become Chamberlain’s foreign secretary, fell prey to Hitler’s deception, too. And Halifax had ample political experience, having successfully negotiated with Mahatma Ghandi as Viceroy of India. Halifax travelled to Berlin in 1937 to meet with Hitler. Their meeting began on an odd note, with Halifax mistaking Hitler for a footman. In the five days Halifax spent in Germany, he also met with two of Hitler’s top ministers, Hermann Göring and Joseph Goebbels. When Halifax returned to England, he was satisfied with the relationships he developed in Germany and confidently believed that Hitler had no intentions of going to war. 
Lord Halifax’s failure to detect deceitfulness in Hitler shows that Hitler was capable of fooling political figures with considerable negotiation experience. This implies that it was something other than Chamberlain’s lack or experience that compromised his ability to read Hitler accurately. Gladwell is suggesting that Hitler’s success, much like that of the Cuban double agents, was less a consequence of his skill or Chamberlain’s naivete as it was humanity’s fundamentally lacking ability to detect deceit.
Themes
Default to Truth Theme Icon
One interesting feature of Hitler’s deception, argues Gladwell, is that not everybody fell for his tricks. Rather counterintuitively, Hitler seemed to fool people who engaged with him closely. In contrast, those who had no relationship with him remained unconvinced. Winston Churchill might have deemed Chamberlain’s negotiations with Hitler “the stupidest thing that has ever been done,” yet Churchill never met Hitler in person. Duff Cooper, one of Chamberlain’s cabinet ministers, immediately saw through Hitler’s performance when Chamberlain relayed the details of their meeting to him afterward. Yet Cooper, like Churchill, never met Hitler in person. Gladwell uses this counterintuitive pattern to conclude that the people who judged Hitler most accurately were the people who knew him least well, and the people whom Hitler fooled were the people who should have known him best. Furthermore, argues Gladwell, such a pattern exists beyond Hitler.
The trend of Hitler fooling people he met in person and failing to fool people who only heard about Hitler’s strategizing secondhand suggests a correlation between the face-to-face encounter and the failure to detect deceit. In other words, something about engaging directly with another person makes us more inclined to trust the words that come out of their mouths than if we were simply to hear those words indirectly, from another person or in writing. Gladwell seems to think that something about the literal act of encountering and interacting with a stranger poises us to want to trust the stranger and our intuitions about the stranger.
Themes
Default to Truth Theme Icon
Self vs. Stranger  Theme Icon
3. Gladwell shifts focus to Solomon, a New York state judge. He describes a scene in which Solomon sits in his courtroom and observes a series of cases involving defendants arrested over the past 24 hours on suspicion of committing a crime. As each defendant approaches the stand, it’s Solomon’s task to determine if a perfect stranger is deserving of freedom or not. Cases with kids are the hardest, admits Solomon, and they’re even harder when he can see the accused’s mother sitting in the gallery. Gladwell compares Solomon’s predicament to that which Neville Chamberlain faced with Hitler in 1938: figuring out how to make sense of a stranger.
Determining whether or not a defendant deserves to be released on bail requires a judge not only to consider the defendant’s legal history, but also to ascertain their trustworthiness. Solomon’s task requires him to read a stranger’s mind and ascertain their trustworthiness and motives based on their outward demeanor. As Gladwell has shown the reader through his analyses of Neville Chamberlain’s misreading of Hitler and the CIA’s misreading of the double agents, such a task leaves considerable room for error.
Themes
Default to Truth Theme Icon
Limitations of Transparency  Theme Icon
Self vs. Stranger  Theme Icon
One of Solomon’s cases involved an older, Spanish-speaking man accused of assaulting his girlfriend’s six-year-old grandson. If Solomon set the man’s bail high, he would go straight to prison—despite his pleas of innocence. Furthermore, the man’s record was virtually unblemished, and he had an ex-wife and 15-year-old son he was supporting. Solomon also considered how unreliable young children can be as witnesses. Faced with an incredibly difficult decision, the best Solomon could do was look the man in the eye and try to determine what kind of person he was. But, asks Gladwell, is such a strategy truly productive?
For Solomon to make a “correct” decision about the Spanish-speaking man, he must reconcile the discrepancies between the young grandson’s accusation, the man’s unblemished record, and the ethical ramifications of depriving the man’s ex-wife and teenage son of financial support. Faced with so much conflicting information, the best Solomon can do is trust that his intuition will tell him whether or not the man will return for trial if released on bail. But, as Gladwell has shown before, our intuitions are subjective and not as reliable as we’d like to think they are.
Themes
Default to Truth Theme Icon
Limitations of Transparency  Theme Icon
Coupling Theory and Context  Theme Icon
4. To answer this question, Gladwell consults a study conducted between 2008 and 2013 by a Harvard economist named Sendhil Mullainathan. Mullainathan and his research team assembled the records for over 500,000 defendants tried in New York State and found that the state had released just over 400,000 of them. Next, Mullainathan programmed an AI system to analyze the same records and curate its own list of which 400,000 people it deemed most worthy of release. In the end, Mullainathan found that the computer’s list of people was 25 percent less likely to commit a crime if released on bail than were the people that human judges deemed safe for release. In fact, human judges released 50 percent of the 1 percent of defendants the computer considered highly likely to commit a crime if released on bail.
The main difference between the computer program’s methods and a human judge’s methods for determining which defendants deserve to be released on bail is the additional independent variable of human intuition. The findings of Mullainathan’s study—that the computer was overwhelmingly more accurate in determining which defendants were likely to commit a crime if released on bail than a human judge—reveals human intuition to be an obstacle rather than an asset to determining bail worthiness. Once more, Gladwell shows how bad humans are at judging strangers.
Themes
Default to Truth Theme Icon
Self vs. Stranger  Theme Icon
How can human judges be so wrong? And how could a computer, which has no access to anything uttered in the courtroom during the arraignment trials, judge the defendants more accurately? Gladwell cites a case study he explored in his second book, Blink, in which orchestras made better recruiting decisions when hiring committees assessed applicants’ auditions from behind a screen. The practice prohibited the committee from forming biases based on applicants’ appearance or race, for example.
In Blink, Gladwell tells the story of Abbie Conant, a professional trombonist who won a position with the Munich Philharmonic Orchestra via a “blind” audition in which judges sat behind a screen and were not aware of her gender, race, or general appearance. Although her playing impressed the judging panel enough to hire her, she experienced gender discrimination throughout her tenure with the orchestra. Conant’s experience is a situation where a face-to-face interaction explicitly diminishes a person’s ability to judge a stranger accurately and fairly. 
Themes
Default to Truth Theme Icon
Limitations of Transparency  Theme Icon
There are more factors to consider in making a bail decision, however. For instance, a judge can factor mental illness into their decision, refusing bail for defendants whose illness might cause them to commit future crimes before their trial can take place. While some information contained in the defendant’s records—such as previous hospitalizations—can provide insight into potential mental instability, however, Solomon argues that one can only ascertain other clues, such as a defendant’s inability to make eye contact, in person. All this leads Gladwell to present Puzzle Number Two, which asks why meeting a stranger makes humans worse at judging their character than not meeting them at all. 
Solomon argues that observing a defendant’s mannerisms is a better indicator of trustworthiness than the objective facts contained within their medical records. The findings of Mullainathan’s study suggest, however, that Solomon is overconfident in his personal ability to make an objective, informed judgment about a defendant.
Themes
Default to Truth Theme Icon
Limitations of Transparency  Theme Icon
Self vs. Stranger  Theme Icon
5. Neville Chamberlain’s final visit with Hitler occurred in September 1938. After Hitler verbally agreed to limit his conquests to the Sudetenland, Chamberlain asked him to sign an agreement attesting to this claim. Hitler enthusiastically signed the paper, and Chamberlain returned to England satisfied that Hitler would honor his promise. Yet, in March 1939, Hitler invaded all of Czechoslovakia.  Less than six months later, he invaded Poland, which led to World War II.
Not only did Chamberlain catastrophically misjudge Hitler’s intentions to start a world war, but he also walked away from the negotiation feeling confident about his success in judging Hitler’s character. Gladwell offers this example of Chamberlain’s botched negotiation with Hitler to demonstrate that humans are monstrously unskilled at judging strangers, as well as an ignorance about their lack of skill.
Themes
Default to Truth Theme Icon
Self vs. Stranger  Theme Icon
Gladwell describes a psychological study, led by Emily Pronin, which asked its subjects to do a word completion task.  When Pronin asked the subjects to comment on what the words they formed said about their personalities, one subject objected to such arbitrary decisions having anything to do with who they were as a person, and many other subjects agreed. However, when Pronin gave the subjects other people’s words, the subjects enthusiastically offered their judgment about what these completions said about the personalities of complete strangers. For instance, one subject surmised that another person’s failure to complete B_ _K with “BOOK” was an indication that they didn’t read much. None of the subjects seemed to realize that they had been tricked into applying a double standard to the way the word completions revealed truths about themselves versus complete strangers.
Pronin’s study reveals that people are overconfident in their ability to judge the inner thoughts of others. At the same time, however, they fail to believe that other people can use the same technique to judge them. These findings suggest that people view themselves as complex and unreadable compared to other people, who are straightforward and easy to read. This double standard could explain why humans are fundamentally bad at reading strangers: because we fail to regard strangers with the same level of nuance and complexity that we project onto ourselves. 
Themes
Self vs. Stranger  Theme Icon
Pronin calls this double standard the “illusion of asymmetrical insight,” and attributes it to the fallacy that we think we know other people better than they know themselves. Gladwell believes the illusion of asymmetrical insight is the problem at the core of the CIA’s inability to identify the Cuban double agents, Chamberlain’s inability to discern Hitler’s deception, and judges’ inability to determine whether a defendant should receive bail. Each case involves a grave overestimation of our ability to know things about a stranger. The purpose of the remainder of this book, explains Gladwell, will be to convince the reader of the fact that “Strangers are not easy.”
Pronin’s “illusion of asymmetrical insight” suggest that misreading strangers is a more complex issue than simply letting personal racist or sexist biases cloud one’s opinion of another. Instead, misreading strangers is the result of the fundamentally flawed way we regard other people. 
Themes
Self vs. Stranger  Theme Icon
Quotes