Thinking, Fast and Slow

Thinking, Fast and Slow

by

Daniel Kahneman

Teachers and parents! Our Teacher Edition on Thinking, Fast and Slow makes teaching easy.

Thinking, Fast and Slow: Part 4, Chapter 26 Summary & Analysis

Summary
Analysis
Kahneman discovered the flaws in Bernoulli’s theory because he noticed that gambles were often spoken of in terms of a few pennies. He wondered if it was possible to assume that people evaluate gambles by tiny differences in wealth. Likewise, Tversky quickly realized that another economist had proposed that utilities were attached to changes of wealth rather than states of wealth.
Kahneman’s discovery that gambling pennies only scratches the surface of how people gamble illuminates the idea that when we gamble, we take into consideration the change to our monetary status. Thus, higher-stakes scenarios are necessary to understand true decision making.
Themes
Human Fallibility and Overconfidence Theme Icon
In utility theory, there is no way to represent the fact that gains and losses have different utilities. These differences were neither expected nor studied. When Kahneman and Tversky casually shifted from speaking about winning to speaking about losing in different thought experiments, they realized that their preferences shifted as well.
The difference between gains and losses becomes the primary evidence for prospect theory’s claim: that people’s choices about gambles are determined less by the inherent value of money, and more by the way their wealth has changed.
Themes
Choices, Losses, and Gains Theme Icon
Kahneman asks readers to consider two problems: 1) Get $900 for sure OR 90% chance to get $1,000; 2) Lose $900 for sure OR 90% chance to lose $1,000. Most people choose the sure thing in the first problem and the gamble in the second. In the second problem the sure loss is very aversive, and this drives people to take the risk. People become risk-seeking when all options are bad. Bernoulli’s theory did not have a way to accommodate this difference.
People dislike the certainty of losing, and in choices between two potential losses, would rather attempt the chance of maintaining their current wealth, even though it means they might eventually lose more money. But for winning, they would rather have a guarantee of improving their wealth than the potential of not gaining any money at all.
Themes
Choices, Losses, and Gains Theme Icon
Kahneman gives two more problems: 1) You are given $1,000. You are then asked to choose between a 50% chance to win an additional $1,000 OR get $500 for sure. 2) You are given $2,000. You are then asked to choose between a 50% chance to lose $1,000 OR lose $500 for sure. In both problems, the final states of wealth are identical. According to Bernoulli’s theory, people should have the same preferences in both. In reality, people are risk-averse in the first problem (choosing the sure thing) and risk-seeking in the second (choosing the gamble).
This example highlights how framing plays into prospect theory. Even though these two outcomes are essentially the same, the reference point (and the fact that we might win or lose) has a big effect on the decisions that people make, demonstrating clearly that we care more about losing than we do about winning.
Themes
Intuition, Deliberation, and Laziness Theme Icon
Choices, Losses, and Gains Theme Icon
Get the entire Thinking, Fast and Slow LitChart as a printable PDF.
Thinking, Fast and Slow PDF
Kahneman and Tversky found three cognitive features at the heart of prospect theory: 1) Evaluation is relative to a neutral reference point—outcomes that are better than the reference points are gains. Below the reference point they are losses. 2) A principle of diminishing sensitivity applies to wealth. The difference between $900 and $1,000 is smaller than the difference between $100 and $200. 3) Losses loom larger than gains.
The three principles cohere into a larger argument that Kahneman makes throughout the book—in this chapter as well as chapter in which he talks about goods rather than money. We care less about the intrinsic value of money, and more about how our wealth changes.
Themes
Choices, Losses, and Gains Theme Icon
Many options we face in life are choices between a risk of loss and opportunity for gain. A simple example is this: if a coin shows tails, you lose $100. If a coin shows heads, you win $150. For most people, the fear of losing is more intense than the hope of gaining. To balance the potential loss of $100, most people require the opportunity to win about $200. The greater the potential loss, the more people usually require to offset that loss in a gamble.
This comparison shows explicitly how the pain of losing is a bigger factor than the joy of winning, because we care more about maintaining our current status than improving it unless it is balanced by a much better prospect (in this case, $200).
Themes
Choices, Losses, and Gains Theme Icon
Quotes
Kahneman points out another flaw in Bernoulli’s theory, proved by Matthew Rabin in 2000. He notes that most Humans reject this gamble: 50% chance to lose $100 and 50% to win 200. According to utility theory, that same Human will also turn down this gamble: 50% chance to lose $200 and 50% chance to win $20,000—but of course, no one would turn down this gamble.
Because utility theory does not account for changes in wealth, it demonstrates that people who are very risk averse are risk averse in every scenario (including ones in which enormous gains are possible). But this is a flaw in the theory: the change in wealth is crucial to understanding why people would take this gamble.
Themes
Choices, Losses, and Gains Theme Icon
Kahneman admits that there are benefits to utility theory, especially in introductory economic texts. The basic concepts of economics are not easy and are also grounded in rationality. Introducing psychology makes those concepts even more complicated.
This is one of the sole concessions that Kahneman makes to the idea of simplifying in order to ease understanding, and acknowledging that economic theory has objective rules, while the human mind is subjective and constantly changing.
Themes
Stories and Subjectivity vs. Statistics and Objectivity Theme Icon
Prospect theory also has flaws. Consider three gambles: A) One chance in a million to win $1 million. B) 90% chance to win $12 and 10% chance to win nothing. C) 90% chance to win $1 million and 10% chance to win nothing. In each case, winning nothing is possible and prospect theory assigns the same value to each instance of winning nothing—a value of zero. In reality, this is true of the first two options, but in the third option the idea of winning nothing is intensely disappointing. Prospect theory does not change the value of an outcome when it is highly unlikely, or when the alternative is valuable.
Prospect theory’s flaws can be attributed to our subjectivity concerning numbers. In addition to losses looming greater than gains, we also begin to attach expectations and assumptions to numbers (in the third case, the assumption that we will win $1 million). This psychological valuation makes pinning down subjective rules in every instance very difficult.
Themes
Stories and Subjectivity vs. Statistics and Objectivity Theme Icon
Choices, Losses, and Gains Theme Icon
Prospect theory and utility theory also fail to allow for regret. Consider problem 6: Choose between 90% chance to win $1 million OR $50 with certainty. Now problem 7: Choose between 90% chance to win $1 million OR $150,000 with certainty. Failing to win is disappointing in both, but problem 7 is made even worse by knowing that if you choose the gamble and lose you will regret the “greedy” decision of not opting for a sure $150,000.
Again, as in the previous example, we have attached our subjective feelings to the outcomes of the gambles—and these feelings will vary both from situation to situation and also from person to person. It is difficult for us to prefer objectivity when we often attach emotional value to goods and money.
Themes
Stories and Subjectivity vs. Statistics and Objectivity Theme Icon
Choices, Losses, and Gains Theme Icon