The Selfish Gene

by

Richard Dawkins

Teachers and parents! Our Teacher Edition on The Selfish Gene makes teaching easy.

The Selfish Gene: Chapter 13 Summary & Analysis

Summary
Analysis
Dawkins thinks that an “uneasy tension” lies at the heart of the gene’s eye view of evolution. On one hand, there is a beguiling picture of genes—immortal coils, or DNA replicators—forming temporary colonies and passing through generations of mortal, throwaway survival machines. On the other hand, there is a coherent sense of each individual as one agent, as one living thing. Dawkins admits that in some chapters he talks about individuals as if they are agents, enacting strategic behaviors to pass on their genes, while in others he presents things from the gene’s “point of view.” He addresses this “paradox” at length in his book The Extended Phenotype. He’s going to offer a short summary of that book here.   
Dawkins acknowledges that the biggest challenge to his selfish gene view of evolution is how hard it is to shake off the notion that individuals are coherent selves. It’s very hard for readers to mentally edit the “individual” out of the picture, even though Dawkins thinks they are nothing more than survival machines, or observable effects of genes in action. He wants to break down distinctions between individuals and others, as well as individuals and the world, to show that the concept of the individual is arbitrary, in order to make his selfish gene view seem more plausible.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
Genes themselves all look alike. Their differences are only made visible by their effects on the embryos they build. These visible “effects” are called phenotypes. The phenotypic effect of one gene might be “green eyes,” or “curly hair,” for example. Natural selection favors genes on the basis of their phenotypic effects.  Darwinians often think of the phenotypic effects as converging in one organism. A gene that makes an individual run faster keeps the individual alive to reproduce, thus benefiting all the genes in that individual. Dawkins rephrases this as “what’s good for one gene is good for all.”
The only way to observe a gene in action is by looking at the effects that it has on an embryo. A “phenotypic effect” is any observable trait that can be traced to a gene. An organism is really just a site where a lot of phenotypic effects converge. Dawkins wants to argue that thinking of an organism as a single entity a mistake. What really matters is the phenotypic effect of the gene. 
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
Dawkins wonders what happens when a gene has a phenotypic effect that’s good for the gene, but bad for the body as a whole. In other words, he’s talking about genes that “cheat.” Geneticist James Crow calls these “genes that beat the system.” For example, t-genes in mice make them sterile or die young, but they also exploit the way that genes are allocated to sperm cells. This is called a “segregation disorder.” When t-genes arise through mutation, they’re in 95 percent of the mouse’s sperm cells (instead of half). They usually cause the population to go extinct.
Dawkins first tries to dismantle the notion of an organism as a unified being by stressing genetic conflicts that go on within an organism. Some genes have phenotypic effects that damage or destroy the organism, such as t-genes in mice, which lead to sterility and, ultimately, to extinction. Dawkins raises this case to show that at the genetic level, the unity of an organism isn’t important—only gene survival matters.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
Dawkins characterizes biologists as people who focus on organisms and ask questions like why they group into societies, and so on. But Dawkins believes that, when one thinks about it, there’s no reason to limit phenotypic effects to a particular individual. In fact, “the phenotypic effects of a gene need to be thought of as all the effects it has on the world.” He wonders this means in practical terms. He suggests that phenotypic effects extending beyond the body can be seen in things like beaver dams, bird nests, and caddis houses. After all, these all help the genes survive too. 
Dawkins argues that phenotypic effects can be observed in the environment as well as on an organism. Building a good nest, for example, also helps a gene survive, so technically the phenotypic effect is visible in the nest itself. He wants to show that the division between individuals and environments is arbitrary.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
Get the entire The Selfish Gene LitChart as a printable PDF.
The Selfish Gene PDF
When caddis flies are larvae at the bottom of a lake, they meticulously build “mobile homes” out of tiny stones and sticks that they protect themselves with like shells. Natural selection favors caddis larvae that build the best protective homes, since this facilitates their survival and reproduction. Dawkins thinks that if a geneticist were to compare the structures of caddis houses, they would be looking at the phenotypic effects of caddis larvae genes. It makes as much sense to think of genes for “stone hardness” or “stone size” in caddis larvae as it does to think about genes for “green eyes” or “wrinkles in peas.” He thinks his logic is “inescapable.”  
Dawkins drills deeper into the example of caddis flies to show the reader how a phenotypic effect breaks down the division between an individual and an environment. Technically, a caddis fly gene programmed the caddis fly to pick certain stones for its “mobile home,” and the choice of stone also contributes to the gene’s survival. Phenotypic effects are really what tests the success of a gene, and these extend beyond the boundaries of a survival machine’s body.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
Dawkins thinks about parasites next. Flukes (flatworms) are parasites that live in snails. They secrete chemicals that make snails build thicker shells. This is beneficial to the fluke (which is better protected inside the thicker shell), but costly to the snail (because it spends energy building a thick shell that could be saved for sustenance and reproduction). Dawkins thinks this means the fluke’s genes have a phenotypic effect on the snail’s shell. He thinks this happens with a lot of parasites, and it means that phenotypic effects extend to other living bodies.
Dawkins then discusses cases in which genes in one organism can have phenotypic effects on another organism’s body. Genes in flatworks make snails build thicker shells. Technically, the thickness of a snail’s shell is a phenotypic effect of a flatworm gene. Here Dawkins argues that the distinction between two individuals (like the distinction between an individual and its environment) is arbitrary.  
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
If a parasite’s genes are transmitted to a new host by way of the host’s reproductive cells, the parasite will do everything it can to keep the host alive and reproducing. Dawkins says, “over evolutionary time it will cease to be a parasite, will cooperate with the host, and may eventually merge into the host’s tissues and become unrecognizable as a parasite at all.”
Many organisms contain parasites that are necessary for the organism to survive. Technically, there are two organisms, but their phenotypic effects converge in one survival machine. Once again, Dawkins wants to dismantle the idea that a body is a unified whole.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
Parasitic bacteria that live in ambrosia beetles seem so essential to the beetle’s reproductive processes that’s hard to consider them parasitic. Like ants and bees, if a beetle egg is unfertilized it will develop into a male embryo. But unlike ants and bees, beetle eggs need to be “pricked” by something to develop into an embryo at all. Parasitic bacteria do the “pricking,” which enables male embryos to develop. In a sense, the bacteria’s own bodies disappear and merge with the host’s bodies. 
Dawkins offers a detailed example to show how thinking of a body as a single entity is wrong. Bacteria that prick beetle eggs to complete the reproductive process are very difficult to separate from the beetle itself, since the beetle wouldn’t exist without the bacteria. Therefore, it almost makes more sense to think of them as one body, rather than two.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
This also happens with sea anemones and algae, and with minute, free-floating DNA fragments called “viroids” or “plasmids” that splice themselves seamlessly into chromosomes in human reproductive cells (and then splice themselves out again in the embryo that’s created). Similarly, venereal disease genes benefit from having their hosts copulate, because this allows the gene to spread and replicate in a new host. In fact, they even benefit from having attractive hosts (which makes copulation more likely).
Dawkins offers further examples of interactions between organisms that converge in one body in order to emphasize that this is a common phenomenon in nature. These cases imply that dividing the world up into “selves” and “others” (or different individuals) doesn’t always make sense. Once again, Dawkins wants to dismantle the notion of an individual a single entity.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
According to Dawkins, phenotypic effects can extend as far as across entire lakes (for example, in beaver dams), and that parasites can influence hosts from afar as well. For example, cuckoos who hatch in other birds’ nests (such as songbird nests) are technically parasites. Dawkins thinks the idea of an organism having its “own body” is a “loaded assumption,” because phenotypic effects can extend far beyond an organism’s “own body” and external parasites (like cuckoos) can manipulate a host’s behavior as much as internal ones can.
Dawkins stresses once again that genes have effects that extend well into the environment. Technically, cuckoo genes control the actions of. A cuckoo gene can have as much impact on a songbird’s actions as a gene inside the songbird’s own body. Dawkins thinks the concept of a body as one unified “thing” is seriously mistaken, since phenotypic effects constantly spill over into different bodies and environments.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
For example, some parasitic ants invade a nest, kill the queen (either by slowly severing her head, or more efficiently, secreting a chemical that makes the workers do it), and take her place, while the unwitting worker ants tend to the parasite’s brood. Similarly, some cocooned caterpillars emit noises, which make ants attach onto their cocoons and fend off predators. Dawkins thinks it doesn’t make sense to talk about individuals and others. One should only be talking about genes and phenotypic effects. His central claim about extended phenotypes is that “an animal’s behavior tends to maximize the survival of the genes ‘for’ that behavior, whether or not those genes happen to be in the body of the particular animal performing it.
Having addressed plants, viruses, bacteria, parasites, mollusks, mammals, and birds, Dawkins now turns to insects to show that his claim applies to the natural world as a whole. Phenotypic effects always extend beyond a single survival machine. In fact, this is such a common phenomenon that the division of the world into selves, others, and environments is inaccurate. The world should be divided into genes and phenotypic effects, because talking about individuals as discrete entities makes scientists (like group selectionists, in Dawkins’s estimation) formulate mistaken accounts of evolution.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
Dawkins suggests that one way to get around the problem of talking about “individuals” is to talk about replicators and vehicles. The fundamental units of evolution are things that replicate. In humans, this is DNA. They “gang together” in communal survival machines, or vehicles. In humans, these vehicles are our bodies. Replicators don’t run around and escape from predators, they make their vehicles do that. Vehicles don’t replicate, they facilitate the propagation of replicators. He thinks biologists focus on the “vehicle,” but they should be focusing on the “replicator.”
Dawkins thinks the mistake that group selectionists make is thinking about evolution as something that happens to “vehicles,” when it’s actually something that happens to “replicators.” Replicators (such as DNA, or genes) team up in vehicles that gather resources for them, but the actual entity that’s evolving is the replicator, not the vehicle.   
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
The Unit of Evolution Theme Icon
For Dawkins, “organism” and “group of organisms” are candidates for the “vehicle” role, but neither are candidates for the “replicator” role. Between individuals and groups, “individuals” win out as vehicles, because the category “group” is too “wishy-washy.” The unity of an individual lion far surpasses the unity of a pride of lions.
Dawkins thinks that by definition, evolution can only get off the ground when there’s a replicating entity. Organisms and species aren’t replicators, but “vehicles,” so the group selectionists are wrong to think that species and not genes evolve.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
The Unit of Evolution Theme Icon
The Extended Phenotype attempts to answer questions about why genes gang up in cells, live in survival machines, and transfer to new hosts via a “bottleneck” route of reproduction. Dawkins briefly sketches out some of those answers here.  
Dawkins thinks the idea of a discrete individual is an illusion created by genes that benefit from teaming up into cells and bodies and making bodies reproduce.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
Cells, to Dawkins, are like pharmaceutical factories. DNA molecules make proteins that work as enzymes (they cause chemical reactions). Each gene makes one type of enzyme. But sometimes multiple enzymes are needed to make a useful product. So, a cell is like a production line that makes an end-product through a series of intermediate steps. Cells essentially keep the genes that cooperate together. However, the cooperating genes aren’t selected as a “group.” They come together by chance, and if their combination doesn’t produce a viable end product, the cell dies. At the bottom of all this behavior is still a single selfish gene that benefits from cooperation with other genes.
It's tempting to think of a cell as a unified entity. But Dawkins thinks that really, cells are more like a “production line” in which multiple genes work together to create a product: a protein wall. If the genes don’t work well together, the end-product is mangled, the protein wall can’t be built, and the genes (little chunks of DNA) can’t protect their molecules from being stolen by other replicators. Even at the cellular level, cooperation only happens among genes if there is a selfish payoff to a single gene.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
Selfishness, Altruism, and Cooperation Theme Icon
Dawkins wonders next why cells clump together into bodies or “lumbering robots.” He remembers that each cell is a clone containing all the genes in the whole body. He decides that cells that club together can “specialize.” Some of them can focus on watching for predators, others can focus on digesting food, and so on. This means that different genes are “turned on” in different cells. The genes that are turned on in one cell benefit their copies that are dormant in other cells.
Dawkins thinks the only reason that bodies exist at all is because it’s more efficient for genes to divide and conquer the work of making a survival machine effective, which benefits all their clone-genes in all the other cells in that survival machines. The teamwork creates the illusion of a single body, but really, the body is just a group of self-interested genes cooperating for mutual benefits.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
Selfishness, Altruism, and Cooperation Theme Icon
Finally, Dawkins wonders why genes propagate through the “bottleneck” route of reproduction. It doesn’t matter how big or complex an organism is— each time, the next generation begins with a new single cell, a fertilized egg. He thinks this is like “going back to the drawing board.” Genes don’t take an existing heart and remodel it into a new one—they grow new ones “inspired” by the previous model. The “growth cycle” of an embryo (including birth and childhood) also allows certain genes to be turned on at certain points in the growth cycle. Dawkins thinks this is necessary for precise and complex organs like bird’s wings or eagle’s eyes to be created. He calls this an “orderly timing cycle.”
It seems like bodies are individuals that create other individuals through reproduction, which all together compile a discrete group. But Dawkins thinks the real reason genes make the world look like this is because building new embryos enables genes to cooperate and build more complex survival machines based on when each gene is activated as the embryo grows. Reproduction, too, is just an example of genes cooperating for the mutual benefit of their own survival.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
Selfishness, Altruism, and Cooperation Theme Icon
The third reason for a bottleneck life cycle is “cellular uniformity.” Evolution happens through cell mutation. Imagine there’s a plant called “splurge-weed” that reproduces by shedding a branch that grows another body. A mutant gene would have to spread one by one into all the cells of the splurge weed before the next shedding happened. But if a mutant gene arises in a single cell that clones itself to make a new body (say, in another imaginary plant called “bottle-wrack”) it’s already automatically going to be in every cell of the embryo that’s built. It’s also more likely the cells in that survival machine will cooperate, since they have the same interest at heart: propagation of the genes inside them. Dawkins thinks the evolutionary payoff of a “bottleneck” reproductive cycle is why there are discrete organisms at all. 
Dawkins gives another reason for why reproduction happens, to show that it’s got nothing to do with making individuals. In fact, it just makes replication more efficient. A gene that mutates before an embryo is created automatically spreads to all the cells in that embryo. That’s much more efficient than a gene that mutates in one cell and then trying to spread to each other cell one by one. Reproduction, in other words, is the most efficient way for a gene to replicate. Dawkins stresses once again that organisms only exist because of genes attempting to propagate themselves.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
There’s a lot more to The Extended Phenotype, but Dawkins hopes he’s given a “flavor” of the book here. He concludes by giving a “brief manifesto” of the “selfish gene/extended phenotype” view of life, which he thinks applies to all living beings, everywhere in the universe. The manifesto begins with the claim that “fundamental unit—the “prime mover of all life”—is the replicator. A replicator is “anything in the universe of which copies are made.” Replicators come into existence by chance, but once they exist, they can make infinite copies of themselves.  
Dawkins takes stock of what he has said so far, to make a larger “manifesto” about evolution in general. He thinks it’s impossible for evolution to happen at all without something that becomes more numerous by making copies of itself (replicating). A replicator can be anything so long as it makes copies or clones of itself: DNA, ideas, maybe even electronic circuits, or silicone. The evolving unit in every context is always the replicator. 
Themes
The Unit of Evolution Theme Icon
Since no copying process is perfect, slightly different replicators will emerge that are better or worse at making copies of themselves. The ones that are best at making copies of themselves “come to dominate the population.” Over time, “the world becomes filled with the most powerful and ingenious replicators.” 
The reason why evolution happens at all is because replicators sometimes make imperfect copies of themselves, which compete with the original replicators over finite resources. Saying that evolution happens is tantamount to saying that replicators compete, and the best ones win.
Themes
The Unit of Evolution Theme Icon
Replicators will find more and more elaborate ways of perpetuating themselves. Replicators survive because of their “consequences on the world.” These can be quite indirect, but as long as they affect the replicator’s success at getting copied, they still count. The success of a replicator depends on the world it’s placed in. One of the most important factors is other replicators. Just like the oarsmen, replicators that work well together to achieve a joint goal will dominate the world.    
The success of a replicator depends on how it gets resources in the world in which it emerges. In many cases, replicators are able to make more copies of themselves when they team up and cooperate. The oarsmen analogy shows that eight oarsmen rowing together are far more likely to win a race than one oarsman rowing by himself. 
Themes
Selfishness, Altruism, and Cooperation Theme Icon
The Unit of Evolution Theme Icon
At some point in time, this “ganging up of mutually compatible replicators” formalized into discrete vehicles: “cells, and later, many celled bodies.” The vehicles that evolved a “bottleneck” life cycle prospered. This made them more “discrete” and “vehicle-like.” This “packaging of living material into discrete vehicles” became so visible that, when biologists started inquiring about the world around them, “their questions were mostly about vehicles—individual organisms.” Dawkins thinks that biology needs to be turned “the right way up” by realizing that replicators came first. He suggests that one way to do this is to remember that phenotypic effects of a gene are not limited to the body it lives in.       
When replicators in the natural world (DNA) team up, or cooperate for better success, they happen to create vehicles (first cells, then bodies, and eventually bodies that reproduce). And when evolutionary biologists started to think about evolution, they saw individual bodies functioning in a world and assumed evolution started there. Dawkins thinks they missed an essential part of the picture: without replicators, there would be no bodies. Bodies are just some of the phenotypic effects of genes (replicators), but there are many more, extending far into the world.
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
The Unit of Evolution Theme Icon
If one use one’s imagination, one can see the gene as “sitting at the centre of a radiating web of extended phenotypic power.”  Similarly, one can imagine every object in the world sitting at the center of several converging webs of influences from many genes sitting in many organisms. The world is “criss-crossed” with arrows joining phenotypic effects to genes. Dawkins concludes that replicators are no longer peppered freely around the universe. They are packaged into individual bodies. Similarly, many phenotypic effects have “congealed” into those bodies instead of being spread evenly throughout the world. But the “individual body” did not have to exist. The only kind of entity that has to exist for life to arise is the immortal replicator
Dawkins suggests that the reader might be able to shift into a mindset of thinking about replicators and phenotypic effects by thinking about a gene as the center of a “web.” Its phenotypic effects extend, like a spider’s web, out into the world, and cross over many other webs. Individuals are really just dense areas where there are many tightly “criss-crossed” or “congealed” webs. There are so many crossovers that the webs almost look like a solid object. What’s really at stake, however, isn’t the congealed web, but the replicator creating that web.   
Themes
The Gene’s Eye View of Evolution Theme Icon
The Unit of Evolution Theme Icon
Quotes